Berkeley on the 'Twofold state of things'

Berkeley writes in his Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous that he 'acknowledge[s] a twofold state of things, the one ectypal or natural, the other archetypal and eternal[.] The former was created in time; the latter existed from everlasting in the mind of God' (254). On a straight...

Full description

Saved in:  
Bibliographic Details
Published in:International journal for philosophy of religion
Main Author: Frankel, Melissa (Author)
Format: Electronic Article
Language:English
Check availability: HBZ Gateway
Journals Online & Print:
Drawer...
Fernleihe:Fernleihe für die Fachinformationsdienste
Published: Springer Science + Business Media B. V [2016]
In: International journal for philosophy of religion
Year: 2016, Volume: 80, Issue: 1, Pages: 43-60
Further subjects:B Divine powers
B Archetype
B Divine Ideas
B Berkeley
B THREE Dialogues Between Hylas & Philonous (Book : Berkeley)
B Archetype (Psychology)
B Skepticism
B PROVIDENCE & government of God
B BERKELEY, George, 1685-1753
Online Access: Volltext (lizenzpflichtig)
Description
Summary:Berkeley writes in his Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous that he 'acknowledge[s] a twofold state of things, the one ectypal or natural, the other archetypal and eternal[.] The former was created in time; the latter existed from everlasting in the mind of God' (254). On a straightforward reading of this passage, it looks as though Berkeley is an indirect perception theorist, who thinks that our sensory ideas are copies or resemblances of archetypal divine ideas. But this is problematic because Berkeley's rejection of scepticism seems partly to rest on a rejection of indirect perception. In this paper, I consider, and reject, three different approaches to solving this problem: (i) that Berkeley's remarks on archetypes are unrepresentative; (ii) that Berkeley is indeed committed to divine archetypal ideas (but that these are in some relevant way different from material archetypes); and (iii) that Berkeley thinks divine archetypal ideas are identical to human ideas. I finally settle on a fourth strategy, which involves reading Berkeley's archetypes as divine powers to produce ideas. I claim that this reading is consistent with the texts, that it has an etymological basis and philosophical precedent, and that it resolves the problems associated with the other three approaches to archetypes.
ISSN:1572-8684
Contains:Enthalten in: International journal for philosophy of religion
Persistent identifiers:DOI: 10.1007/s11153-015-9541-2